Skip to content

Blog post

Keeping scepticism alive in health care improvement

People working in improvement need to be sceptical about health care. They often question and examine longstanding practices. Polly Mitchell, Alan Cribb, and Vikki Entwistle argue that the institutionalisation of improvement can get in the way of this scepticism, allowing costly or even harmful activities to slip under the radar. They explore the role that philosophy can play in upholding an active culture of scepticism in health care improvement.

Read comments 3

Scepticism and health care improvement

Health care improvement activities seek to improve health care processes and outcomes. Often this involves challenging and investigating established ways of working. Just because health care practices are widespread or institutionally embedded doesn’t mean they actually benefit patients. Accepted practices can be based on convention, simplicity, or the insistence of powerful actors, rather than empirical evidence.

In other words, scepticism is at the heart of health care improvement.
Improvement is not sceptical for its own sake: it also generates high-quality evidence about what works well and what does not. This informs changes designed to improve health care processes and outcomes.

Institutional limits on scepticism in practice

Unfortunately, health care improvement activities often don’t improve health care. Many well-designed improvement efforts yield no benefits, and those that do usually have modest effects. Improvement efforts can be poorly coordinated, so that changes which result in benefits in one area can make things worse elsewhere. Hard-won marginal gains in specific areas of clinical practice can be undermined by systemic crises like workforce shortages, chronic under-investment in public health and social care, and lack of pandemic preparedness.

These problems are relatively well recognised, and some responses to them come from within health care improvement: improvement researchers adopt sceptical perspectives towards improvement itself, studying when and why interventions work – and when they don’t.

Implementation scientists promote the systematic uptake of evidence-based improvement findings, identifying ways to surmount the barriers that obstruct this in practice. More critically, sociologists have identified how power and status influence improvement practice and highlighted the reductiveness of efforts that treat complex, dynamic, human health care systems as mechanical and linear processes.

These sceptical currents support debate about how improvement is done, but the value of improvement as a practice remains largely unquestioned within policy and service contexts, and other key aspects go unchallenged.

Improvement activities use up resources, including the time and energy of professionals. Their opportunity costs as well as their direct costs need to be considered alongside their benefits.

At least sometimes it will be better not to pursue improvements at all. Aspects of widespread improvement practices may also have unintended bad consequences, such as placing undue emphasis on more measurable goals and values while overlooking others.

Health care improvement has become institutionalised. As part of their training, junior doctors must carry out clinical audits or quality improvement projects. Departments, teams, and professionals with a specific quality improvement remit sit within most health care organisations. Improvement activities are incentivised and disincentivised by government payment structures and penalties. Personal incentives relating to promotion, pay, and status within health care organisations are therefore attached to improvement activities being carried out.

These factors can make improvement activities an assumed norm, rather than having to be assessed on their merits. This is reinforced by the popular ideal of “continuous improvement” and the oft-repeated mantra of Paul Batalden and Frank Davidoff: “Everyone in health care really has two jobs when they come to work every day: to do their work and to improve it”.

If greater justification is demanded for not doing improvement rather than doing it, then it can be difficult to push back on questionable improvement projects and practices.

In practice, then, there are sometimes limits to the scepticism that health care improvement as a field will take seriously.

Philosophical scepticism and improvement

Philosophy has an important role to play in helping scepticism to thrive in improvement.

Philosophical scepticism can be used to point out and examine assumptions and conventions.

This is done not to undermine improvement activities or knowledge, but to reflect on what is valuable and important and the extent to which this is reflected in the work.

Sceptical questioning can be counter-cultural and difficult to entertain because it calls fundamental tenets of the field into doubt. Could greater improvements in health outcomes be secured by shifting the focus away from health care institutions and towards preventative medicine and the social determinants of health? Should continuous improvement be downplayed in areas of good practice while there are still domains in which care and system functioning is inadequate? And is continuous improvement a desirable aim at all: at a certain point, should health care be deemed good enough, and the pursuit of further improvements considered unjustified when they have significant opportunity costs in other areas of social policy? Can critical currents in health care improvement studies also tend to reify certain values and make unjustified assumptions about which improvement concerns matter most?

Philosophy is well-placed to foster and explore the implications of such forms of scepticism. As a discipline, philosophy is characterised by unusual methodological flexibility, often engaging in ‘meta-methodological’ debate about the nature and limits of the research methods used in other disciplines. This promotes openness about the kinds of questions that can be asked and enables a wide scope of objects of study. Including philosophers in health care improvement work strengthens the ‘skill mix’ in unconventional ways.

Philosophers can inhabit a ‘trickster’ role. Tricksters are archetypal characters who question norms and authority and playfully disrupt the established order. Like tricksters, philosophers adopt, and can encourage others to adopt, questioning, critical attitudes towards the world, challenging established concepts, categories, and institutions.

Philosophers—along with others, including patients and academics from other critical disciplines—can also occupy an ‘insider-outsider’ stance.  As insiders, philosophers can take the realities of health care and improvement as a starting point. This ensures that their work is meaningful and intelligible to practitioners.

At the same time, as outsiders, who are typically not paid or employed by health care or improvement organisations, philosophers can question the current goals and characteristics of practice and raise the possibility of more transformative change. These are questions that it might be difficult for ‘insiders’ to improvement practice to put forward.

Philosophers can make a difference as sceptical friends of improvers—prompting them to think about the ways in which their own sceptical practice risks becoming ossified and, over time, becoming shaped by disciplinary and institutional norms and values.

An openness to philosophy and exploration of radical and transformative ideas can help the field of improvement face its own crises of legitimacy as well as the challenges facing health care systems.

Comments

  1. “Health care improvement activities often don’t improve health care.” Brilliant blog from the talented team here who argue for scepticism in implementation science. In paediatrics, Alan Cribb and I made a similar case for "critical and conscientious" child health here: https://ep.bmj.com/content/106/6/370

    Thank you for articulating the importance of philosophy to health systems research and practice so clearly!

  2. For discussion

    Polly Mitchell, Alan Cribb, and Vikki Entwistle Thank you for an interesting paper. I do agree with most of what you have to say. There are some points, though, that I would like to discuss further, these are miss conceptions held by people in healthcare generally and certainly by many of the commentators on healthcare improvement.

    You refer to ‘complex, dynamic, human health care systems’. First this is a very broad statement. ‘Systems’ are made up of ‘processes’ and ‘processes’ are made up of ‘tasks’. Some of those tasks are more mechanistic than humanistic and some are complicated and may require some procedural documentation (a ‘procedure’). Some tasks are clinical but most are not. All processes, both clinical and non-clinical, can be represented simply by a series of sequential tasks. I do agree that some clinical procedures (tasks) can result in a ‘complex’ and ‘dynamic’ situation but are not themselves complex and dynamic. In these situations the aviation industries ‘Crew Resource Management’ (CRM) techniques come into play. Also in these situations it can be difficult to differentiate between process and procedure. Because of the misrepresentation of these terms in healthcare it is impossible to move forward with proper ‘improvement’.

    For example a process that is desperately in need of ‘improvement’ is the Discharge Summary process. I’m not sure that this process can be described as a complex, dynamic, human health care system. It should be designed as a simple process.

    You say that ‘at a certain point, should health care be deemed good enough, and the pursuit of further improvements considered unjustified.’ That should never be the case. A clear understanding of what we are trying to improve must, though, be understood. There are two different aspects that require improvement (There is a third; I’ll talk about that later). In manufacturing it is easy to differentiate between the two. One is the ‘product’ and the other is the product ‘realisation system’. That differentiation is more difficult in healthcare where the two can easily merge into one. Clearer understanding is required here. Improvement of these two different aspects requires a different approach, tools, and regulations. The ‘product’ in healthcare is much less tangible than in manufacturing and could do with more consideration to provide a better definition. Certain elements of healthcare deliverables could be considered as products i.e. diagnosis report, X ray, and Discharge Summary, but it is predominantly the delivery of diagnosis, tests, treatment and care to patients, which I guess is a Service.

    The ‘realisation system’ is the series of process that change inputs into outputs. In manufacturing that is the production line and in healthcare it’s the patient pathway.

    In manufacturing continuous improvement (CI) is used to improve the ‘realisation system (processes) and re-design or changes to the product specification are used to improve the product, both requiring different techniques and skills. The Production Team improves the realisation system and the Product Design Team improves the product. In the NHS there is just Quality Improvement (QI) which does not differentiate between product and realisation system nor understand the difference and Front Line Staff (FLS) undertake QI. Product (treatment and care) improvement is another area that could do with more consideration to provide a better definition in healthcare. ‘Quality’ is applied to patient outcomes and not the realisation system processes required in achieving those outcomes.

    NICE, GIRFT and University Research undertake the healthcare equivalent of product improvement but there is no easy path in healthcare delivery to implement these improvements.

    There is no CI in healthcare. In order to undertake CI you first require a clear understanding of the ‘realisation system’ and the ‘processes’ required for it to work. To improve a process you need to start form a clear baseline. Because processes are not documented and standardised it is impossible to improve them effectively or sustainable. This can NOT be achieved using the current QI processes and techniques adopted by the NHS.

    If what I’m saying is true then most of what was said @Quality2024 last week was misguided and based on a misconception. I’m not sure that any of the presenters new anything about Quality Management and improvement.

    The third aspect of Service/Product delivery, previously referred to, is Customer Service. For manufactured products it’s mainly the Sales Team that come into contact with the Customer. In healthcare it’s almost everyone but particularly FLS and is required throughout the realisation system.

    1. Last paragraph but one should be 'Quality Management and Continuous Improvement'.

Leave a comment

If you have a Q account please log in before posting your comment.

Read our comments policy before posting your comment.

This will not be publicly visible